Many students of perception believe that experience plays a major role in the genesis of depth perception in the case of the pictorial cues. For example, linear perspective—–the converging projection of parallel contours receding into the distance—–is far more prevalent in the constructed environment of modern society than it is in the more natural environment in which Homo sapiens evolved. Therefore it is not likely that linear perspective would have evolved as an innate sign of depth. But how would we have learned to perceive depth on the basis of linear perspective? Simply by moving around in the world and discovering that what had appeared to be converging lines in a frontal plane are actually receding parallel lines? This would assume that knowledge about the world can affect our perceptions of it, which, as we have seen, is contrary to the nature of perception. A better explanation is the following. When, as children, we first view parallel lines in depth and receive the image of converging lines, we also have available other sensory information about depth from cues such as retinal disparity, convergence, and accommodation. These physiological cues produce veridical perception of the parallel lines. At this point, linear perspective is not functioning as a cue. But it is present. Therefore, we can associate the converging pattern with parallel lines in depth. Because of this association, later on, the converging pattern by itself can evoke the interpretation of parallel lines in depth. It thus would have become a learned cue.